Countably Compact, Countably Tight, Non-Compact Spaces by James Dabbs A thesis submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Auburn University in partial ful llment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Science Auburn, Alabama August 6, 2011 Keywords: Countable Compactness, Countable Tightness, Stone- Cech Compacti cation, Monads Copyright 2011 by James Dabbs Approved by Gary Gruenhage, Chair, Professor, Mathematics & Statistics Michel Smith, Professor, Mathematics & Statistics Stewart Baldwin, Professor, Mathematics & Statistics Randall Holmes, Professor, Mathematics & Statistics Abstract In this work, we will study several examples of countably compact, countably tight, non- compact spaces. After reviewing the important basic notions, we will examine a construction of several such spaces rst given by Manes in \Monads in Topology" and will then detail how to construct such spaces using a more direct and explicit topological process. We will then use this new framework to describe several new spaces and to prove several propositions which are much more transparent from this new viewpoint. ii Acknowledgments First I would like to thank my advisor, Dr. Gary Gruenhage, whose excellent classes reinvigorated my interest in general topology and whose guidance has been invaluable in preparing this work. I would also like to thank the rest of my committee members, Dr. Michel Smith, Dr. Stewart Baldwin and Dr. Randall Holmes for their intellectual stimulation and assistance both in and out of the classroom. I must also o er my sincerest thanks to my family, especially my parents Ricky and Mary Lou Dabbs. Their constant encouragements to focus on my studies and to be a lifelong learner have become guiding principles in my personal development, and I am forever indebted to the opportunities they have a orded me. I would also like to thank my grandparents for their unfaltering encouragement. Finally, I would like to thank my girlfriend McCall Langford and all my friends for their support when I needed to focus on my work and their diversions when I needed not to. iii Table of Contents Abstract . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ii Acknowledgments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . iii 1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 2 Background De nitions and Theorems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 3 Monads of Ultra lters and Their Algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 3.1 Tp! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 4 Topological Descriptions and Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 4.1 pX . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 4.2 UX . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 5 Applications of the Topological Viewpoint . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27 Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 iv Chapter 1 Introduction A vast body of literature is devoted to the study of compact Hausdor spaces. The class of compact Hausdor spaces is well behaved in many important ways, but there is at least one sense in which compact Hausdor spaces may be quite poorly behaved: any metric space is sequential, i.e. the topology is entirely determined by convergent sequences in the space, but there are non-trivial compact Hausdor spaces with no non-trivial convergent sequences. A natural question is: are there topological spaces satisfying a weaker form of compactness but which are to some degree determined by sequences in the space? In this work, we will single out countable compactness as the weaker form of compactness under consideration. When considering countable compactness, there is a natural question: what can be said about spaces which are countably compact but not compact? For instance, no such space can be Lindel of. The speci c question \is every separable, countably compact, countably tight space compact?" was posed as a \classic problem" by Nyikos in [2]. A series of examples of countably compact, countably tight, non-compact spaces satisfying successively stronger separation properties has been constructed [3] [4], but most such constructions require the assumption of additional axioms beyond ZFC. The strongest such example currently known to exist in ZFC was constructed by Manes in [1] using the category-theoretical concept of a monad. In this work, we will give a construction of the spaces rst described by Manes using a new and more explicit topological approach. In Chapter 2, we review the basic background notions. In Chapter 3, we summarize Manes? construction using monads. In Chapter 4, we will detail the new topological construction of Manes? spaces and prove, using our description, that they give examples of countably compact, countably tight, non-compact spaces and 1 discuss their other properties. We will also use this topological framework to construct a new larger class of spaces with many similar properties. Finally, in Chapter 5, we will discuss some applications of this new framework by providing several propositions and constructions that would be either much more opaque or outright impossible from the categorical perspective. 2 Chapter 2 Background De nitions and Theorems The material in this section is standard and can be found in any introductory topology book, but de nitions and proofs can be found in [5]. Basic set theory notions are assumed, and whenever unspeci ed, notation matches that used in [5]. The following terms are well known and will be used without further comment: topol- ogy, topological space, subspace topology, ner topology, open set, neighborhood, closed set, limit point, closure, sequence, continuous function, homeomorphism, compact, T1, Hausdor , regular, completely regular, connected, dense. We will often consider two di erent topologies on the same space. For clarity, we make the following de nition: De nition 2.1. If is a topology on a set X and A X, cl (A) is the closure of A in (X; ). More speci cally: cl (A) =\fCjA C;XnC2 g We may use cl(A) or simply A if is clear from context. Throughout this chapter, X will denote an arbitrary topological space. The following propositions are well known: Proposition 2.2. If C X is closed and X is compact, then C is compact. Proposition 2.3. If C X is compact and X is Hausdor then C is closed in X. Proposition 2.4. If C X is compact and f : X !Y is continuous then f(C) Y is compact. 3 Proposition 2.5. If xn!x in X and f : X!Y continuous then f(xn)!f(x) in Y. Proposition 2.6. If D X is dense, Y is Hausdor , and f;g : X !Y are continuous with fjD = gjD, then f = g. The following de nitions are less widely known, and so they are included for complete- ness: De nition 2.7. X is Urysohn provided that for every pair of points x;y2X there are open sets Ux;Uy X with x2Ux and y2Uy with Ux\Uy =;. Note that any Urysohn space is clearly Hausdor . De nition 2.8. X is extremally disconnected if for every open O X, O is open. The next several results outline the basic construction of and results about the Stone- Cech compacti cation. Proofs are omitted, but may be found in [7]. De nition 2.9. A lter F on a set S is a collection of nonempty subsets of S such that: If A;B2F then A\B2F. If A2F and C A then C2F. De nition 2.10. An ultra lter u on a set S is maximal lter on S. Note that we must appeal to some form of the Axiom of Choice to show that ultra lters exist. By using Zorn?s Lemma, any lter can be extended to an ultra lter. Proposition 2.11. Let F be a lter on a set S. The following are equivalent: 1. F is an ultra lter. 2. For every A S, either A2F or SnA2F. 3. If A[B = S, then either A2F or B2F. 4 4. If A S and A\B6=; for every B2F, then A2F. De nition 2.12. C X is a zero-set in X if there is a continuous f : X ! R with C = f 1(0). De nition 2.13. A z- lter is a lterF on X so that for every C2F, C is a zero-set in X. De nition 2.14. A z-ultra lter is a lter which is maximal among z- lters. De nition 2.15. For x2X, prin(x) =fB XjB a zero-set, x2Bg. A z-ultra lter of the form prin(x) is called a principal ultra lter. De nition 2.16. X is the set of all z-ultra lters on X. The standard topology on X is de ned as follows: if F X is a zero-set, let F = fu 2 X jF 2 ug. A basis for the standard topology consists of all sets of the form XnF for F a zero-set in X. We will primarily consider the case when X is discrete, in which case every subset is a zero-set and X can be described more simply as the set of all ultra lters on X with basic open sets of the form O for any O X. We will typically regard X as a subset of X by identifying x2X with prin(x)2 X. With this identi cation, Proposition 2.17. X X is dense. Proposition 2.18. X is a compact Hausdor space. If X is a completely regular, Hausdor space, the inclusion map X ,! X is an embed- ding and X is often referred to as the Stone- Cech compacti cation of X. Proposition 2.19. If Y is any compact Hausdor space and f : X !Y is a continuous function, there is a unique continuous function F : X !Y so that FjX = f. Moreover, this property uniquely characterizes X. 5 Proposition 2.20. If C;D X are disjoint zero-sets, then cl X(C) and cl X(D) are dis- joint. De nition 2.21. ! is the rst in nite ordinal. Proposition 2.22. j !j= 22!. Proposition 2.23. If X is discrete, X contains no non-trivial convergent sequences. That is, any sequence that converges in X is eventually constant. De nition 2.24. If f : X!Y and u2 X, then f(u) =fB Y jf 1(B)2ug=fC Y jC f(A) for some A2ug. The notation fu is often used in place of f(u). De nition 2.25. X = XnX with the subspace topology inherited from X. Thus an element of X is a non-principal ultra lter. Such an ultra lter is often called free. Proposition 2.26. Let p2! . p contains no nite subsets of !. Proof. Suppose there is some nite F 2p of smallest cardinality. If jFj> 1 and n2F, then either fng2p or Fnfng2p by 2.11.2, contradicting the minimality of jFj. Thus F =fngfor some n2! and so for every B !, with n2B, B2p since p is a lter. Thus p = prin(n) and so p62! . De nition 2.27. A set S X is a weak P-set in X if for every countable C X with C\S =;, C\S =;. De nition 2.28. A point x2X is a weak P-point in X if fxg X is a weak P-set in X. An important fact which we will use frequently is: Proposition 2.29. There are weak P-points in ! . 6 In fact, ! contains a dense set of weak P-points [7], but we will not have need of this stronger result. A central notion in this work is that of a p-limit: De nition 2.30. If p 2 ! and (xn) is a sequence in X, then a point y 2 X is the p- limit of (xn), denoted y = p-limxn provided that for every open O X containing y, fn2!jxn2Og2p. The de nition of a p-limit depends essentially on the topology of X. We may use p- limXxn or p-lim xn to emphasize the space X or topology with respect to which the limit is taken. Note that if xn !x in the usual sense then for any open O about x, fnjxn 2Og is co nite in ! and so this set is in every p2! by 2.26. Thus the notion of a p-limit is a weakening of the usual notion of a limit. The importance of p-limits can be seen in the following proposition: Proposition 2.31. Let (xn) be a sequence in X. y2fxng if and only if y = p-limxn for some p2 !. Proof. Suppose y = p-limxn. Then for any open O containing y,fnjxn2Og2p and since every set in p is nonempty, O\fxng6=; and y2fxng. Conversely, if y 2fxng, let F = ffn j xn 2 Ogj O a neighborhood of yg. For any A;B2F, A\B2F and soF can be extended to an ultra lter p2 !. Then by de nition, for any neighborhood O of y, fnjxn2Og2F p and so y = p-limxn. Let us record a few basic facts about p-limits: Proposition 2.32. Let (xn) be a sequence in X and p2! . If X is Hausdor , then p-limxn is unique if it exists. Proof. Suppose x and y are both p-limits of (xn). If X is Hausdor , there are open Ux;Uy containing x and y respectively with Ux\Uy = ;. Since x is a p-limit of (xn), the set 7 Ax = fnjxn 2Uxg2p and similarly Ay = fnjxn 2Uyg2p. But Ax\Ay = ; since Ux\Uy =;, which contradicts the fact that p is a lter. Thus we are justi ed in referring to \the" p-limit of a sequence. Proposition 2.33. Let (xn) be a sequence in X, p 2 ! and x = p-limxn. For any continuous f : X!Y, f(x) = p-limf(xn). Proof. Let f : X !Y be continuous and O Y be an open neighborhood of f(x). Then x2f 1(O), which is open since f is continuous. Since x = p-limxn, fnjxn2f 1(O)g = fnjf(xn)2Og2p as required. Proposition 2.34. Let (xn), (yn) be sequences in X and p2! . If fnjxn = yng2p then p-limxn = p-limyn. Proof. Suppose A = fnjxn = yng2p. For any open neighborhood O of p-limxn, B = fnjxn2Og2p. Since p is a lter, A\B2p and for every n2A\B, yn = xn2O. Thus A\B fnjyn2Og2p since p is a lter and so p-limxn = p-limyn. De nition 2.35. For p2! , X is p-compact if for every sequence (xn) in X, p-limxn2X (in particular, p-limxn exists). p-compactness is a weakening of compactness: Proposition 2.36. If X is compact, then X is p-compact for every p2! . Proof. Let (xn) be a sequence in X. For B !, let xB =fxnjn2Bg. Then for any p2! , fxBjB2pgis a collection of closed subsets of X with the nite intersection property. Since X is compact, there is some x2\fxB jB2pg. Let O be an open neighborhood of x and A = fnjxn 2Og. For every B2p, x2xB, so there is some n2B with xn 2O. Thus A\B6=;for each B2p and since p is an ultra lter, A2p by 2.11.4. Thus x = p-limxn. De nition 2.37. X is ultracompact if X is p-compact for every p2! . 8 p-compactness can be used to de ne an important partial order on !: De nition 2.38. For p;q2! , the Comfort preorder C on ! is de ned by p C q () every q-compact space is p-compact. De nition 2.39. For p;q2! , the Rudin-Keisler preorder RK on ! is de ned by p RK q () p = fq for some f : !!!. De nition 2.40. X is countably compact if every countable open cover has a nite subcover. Proposition 2.41. If X is p-compact and T1, then X is countably compact. Proof. If X is p-compact, then every in nite set has a limit point by 2.31. Since X is T1, it is countably compact by [5]. Proposition 2.42. If X is countably compact and fCn jn2!g is a countable collection of nonempty closed sets such that Cn+1 Cn, then \Cn6=;. Proof. Let Un = XnCn. Each Un is open. If\Cn =;then[Un = Xn\Cn = X sofUngis a cover. If X is countably compact, there is some N2! so that\n NCn = Xn[n NUn =;, contrary to the assumption that \n NCn = CN 6=;. De nition 2.43. X is sequential if for every non-closed A X, there is a sequence (xn) in A with xn!x62A. A sequential space is one in which the topology is entirely determined by convergent sequences. Using p-limits we can weaken this de nition in the obvious way: De nition 2.44. For p2! , a space X is p-sequential if for every non-closed A X, there is a sequence (xn) in A with p-limxn62A. We can weaken this even further to get the following de nition: De nition 2.45. X is countably tight if for every set A X and x2A, there is some countable C A with x2C. 9 That this is a weaker notion will be shown shortly, but rst let us introduce some notation to aid in the proof: De nition 2.46. For Y X and S ! , de ne AX (S;Y) for each !1 by trans nite induction as follows: AX0 (S;Y) = Y AX +1(S;Y) =fx2Xjx = p-limxn for some p2S and some sequence (xn) in AX (S;Y)g for successor ordinals AX (S;Y) =[ < A (S;Y) for limit ordinals We may write A (S;Y) if X is clear from context. Proposition 2.47. Let p2! . If X is p-sequential and Y X, then clX(Y) = AX!1(fpg;Y). Proof. Fix Y X. Suppose that AX!1(fpg;Y) is not closed. Then since X is p-sequential, there is some sequence (xn) in AX!1(fpg;Y) with p-limxn 62AX!1(fpg;Y). But then by con- struction, there is some !, sojUj>j![fpgj, a contradiction. With what we have established so far about Tp!, we can answer a question posed by Manes in [1]. De nition 5.2. p2! is an m-point if Gp! (Tp!. Manes showed that there is an m-point if we assume the Continuum Hypothesis and further conjectured that every p2! is an m-point in ZFC. We will prove Manes? conjecture using some tools from [9]. The key idea lies in the following: De nition 5.3. If is a semigroup operation on !, we may extend to a semigroup operation on !. The extension, also denoted , may be de ned as follows: for m2! and q2! , let m q = q-limm n as n ranges over !; for p;q2! , let p q = p-limm q as m ranges over !. 27 Proposition 5.4. No p2! is an m-point. Proof. Pick any p 2 ! . By [9, 2.1], Tp! = p! = fq 2 ! j q C pg is always a sub- semigroup under , while Gp! =fq2 !jq = fp for some f : !!!g=fq2!jq RK pg is never a sub-semigroup [9, 2.15]. We can also say a little bit more about the interplay between the order C, the semigroup operation and the topology on p!. The next result says, in e ect, that for any p2! there is an r C p that is \in nitely right-divisible" by p: Proposition 5.5. For any s2! and p2! , there is some q C p so that for every n2!, q = sn r pn for some r C p. Proof. Fix s2! and p2! . As observed in [9], the map f : !! ! by r7!s r p is continuous. By [9, 2.1], p! ! is a subsemigroup under , so f restricts to a function f : p!! p!. If C p! is closed and (xn) is a sequence in f 1(C) then f(p-limxn) = p- limf(xn)2C since C is p-compact. Thus, since p! is p-sequential, f 1(C) is closed and so f is still continuous in the new topology on p!. For each m2!, fm( p!) = sm p! pm is p-compact and thus closed in p! since for each m2!, p-limsm rn pm = p-limfm(rn) = fm(p-limrn)2fm( p!). Thus p! s p! p s2 p! p2 ::: is a countable descending chain of closed subsets of a countably compact space. Thus by 2.42 there is some q2\sn p! pn. Such a q has the property given in the statement. We?ve seen that TpX and pX de ne the same topological spaces when X is a discrete space, but pX can be de ned for any arbitrary space X. This gives us more exibility and allows us to construct examples that could not be constructed using the monads Tp alone. Fix a free ultra lter p2! . Proposition 5.6. For any set X, TpX contains no non-trivial convergent sequences. 28 Proof. Let X be a set. This proposition can be seen from the de nition of TpX, but in light of 4.18, it is easier to see that pX contains no non-trivial convergent sequences when X is considered as a discrete space: since the topology on pX is ner than the standard subspace topology, the inclusion map i : pX ! X is continuous. If a sequence (xn) converges in pX, then (i(xn)) converges in X by 2.5 and so i(xn) is eventually constant by 2.23. Proposition 5.7. There is a space X so that UXnX contains a non-trivial convergent sequence. Proof. By [10], there is a completely regular space X so that X contains a non-trivial convergent sequence. Let xn!x be that sequence. We claim that xn!x in UX as well. For any p2! , p-limxn exists because UX is p-compact. If p-limxn = y6= x then let Ux and Uy be disjoint open sets in X around x and y respectively. Since xn!x,fnjxn2Uyg is nite and thus fnjxn2Uyg62p by 2.26 since p2! . Suppose (xn) does not converge to x in UX. Then there is some open O UX so that A =fnjxn62Ogis in nite. Fix an ultra lter p2! with A2p. Fix z62O and let x0n = xn if xn62O and x0n = z otherwise. Then by 2.34, p-lim Xxn = p-lim Xx0n62O since XnO is ultracompact. In particular p-lim Xxn6= x, contradicting the fact that xn!x in X. Proposition 5.8. For any set X, TpX is extremally disconnected. Proof. Let X be a discrete space. It su ces to show that pX is extremally disconnected. Let be the standard topology on X. Suppose B;C X with B\C =;and B[C = X. We claim that cl p(B)\cl p(C) =; and cl p(B)[cl p(C) = p!. First, since p is ner than , cl p(B) cl (B). Thus cl p(B)\cl p cl (B)\cl (C) =; by 2.20. To prove the second assertion, recall that by 2.47 pX = AY!1(fpg;X) where Y is the space ( X; p). So it su ces to show that A (fpg;X) A (fpg;B)[A (fpg;C) for all < !1 (the reverse inclusion is clear). Note that A0(fpg;X) = A0(fpg;B)[A0(fpg;C). If A (fpg;X) A (fpg;X) [A (fpg;X) for all < and is a limit ordinal, then 29 A (fpg;X) A (fpg;X)[A (fpg;X) trivially. On the other hand, if = + 1 for some and if a2A (fpg;X) then a = p-limxn for some sequence (xn) in A (fpg;X). By the induction hypothesis, (xn) is a sequence in A (fpg;B)[A (fpg;C). Let B0 = fnjxn 2 A (fpg;B)g and C0 = fnjxn 2A (fpg;C)g. B0[C0 = X, so by 2.11.3 we may assume without loss of generality that B02p . Fix z2A (fpg;B) and de ne x0n = xn if n2B0 and x0n = z otherwise. Then (x0n) is a sequence in A (fpg;B) and so p-limx0n2A (fpg;B). But since fnjxn = x0ng2p, by 2.34 a = p-limxn = p-limx0n2A (fpg;B) as required. Now suppose U pX is open. Then since X is dense in pX, cl p(U) = cl p(U\X). By the above, cl p(U\X) = pXncl p(XnU), so cl p(U) is open and pX is extremally disconnected. Proposition 5.9. For any connected, completely regular, Hausdor space X, pX is con- nected. Proof. Suppose X satis es the hypotheses. Since X is connected, clY (X) is connected for any space Y X [5]. pX = clY (X) where Y is the space ( X; p) for the standard topology on X. Thus this new topological method allows us to describe a signi cantly larger class of examples. 30 Bibliography [1] E. Manes, Monads in topology, Topology Appl. 157 (2010), 961-989. [2] P. Nyikos, Classic problems - 25 years later (part 2), Topology Proc. 27 (2003), 365-378. [3] P. Nyikos and J. Vaughn, The Scarborough-Stone problem for Hausdor spaces, Topol- ogy Appl. 44 (1992), 309-316. [4] A. Dow, A countably compact, countably tight, non-sequential space, Proceedings of the 1988 Northeast Conference on General Topology and Applications (1990), 71-80. [5] A. Munkres, Topology, Prentice Hall, 1975. [6] A. Kombarov, Compactness and sequentiallity with respect to a set of ultra lters, Moscow Univ. Math. Bull. 40 (1985), 15-18. [7] J. van Mill, An introduction to !, Handbook of Set-Theoretic Topology 1984, 503-567. [8] S. Mac Lane, Categories for the working mathematician, Springer-Verlag, 1971. [9] S. Garcia-Ferreira, N. Hindman, D. Strauss, Orderings of the Stone- Cech remainder of a discrete semigroup, Topology Appl. 97 (1999) 127-148. [10] R. Fri c and P. Vojt a s, Convergent Sequences in X, Proceedings of the 11th Winter School on Abstract Analysis, Circolo Matematico di Palermo (1984), 133-137. 31